000 04256namaa2200433uu 4500
001 oapen52999
003 oapen
005 20240507100310.0
006 m o d
007 cr|mn|---annan
008 220218s2022 xx |||||o ||| 0|eng d
020 _a9780367340599
020 _a9780429323713
020 _a9781032133539
040 _aoapen
_coapen
041 0 _aeng
042 _adc
072 7 _aJKV
_2bicssc
072 7 _aLAZ
_2bicssc
072 7 _aNHB
_2bicssc
100 1 _aPifferi, Michele
_4edt
245 1 0 _aThe Limits of Criminological Positivism
_bThe Movement for Criminal Law Reform in the West, 1870-1940
260 _bTaylor & Francis
_c2022
300 _a1 online resource
336 _atext
_btxt
_2rdacontent
337 _acomputer
_bc
_2rdamedia
338 _aonline resource
_bcr
_2rdacarrier
506 0 _aFree-to-read
_fUnrestricted online access
_2star
520 _aThe reform agenda promoted by the late-nineteenth-century penal reformers variously described as advocates of 'positivism', 'social defense' or as members of the 'modern' or 'sociological' school of criminal law threatened to erode the boundary separating criminal justice from extra-judicial forms of social control. Focusing on the German case, this essay investigates the debates between Imperial Germany's 'modern' and 'classical' schools of criminal law over two questions that posed particularly stark challenges to the dividing line between criminal justice and extra-judicial forms of state intervention: (1) the implications of determinism for the question of legal responsibility, and (2) the implications that making 'dangerousness' the key criterion for punishment had for the nature of criminal justice and the relationship of judicial and extra-judicial measures of intervention. After analyzing these debates, the essay examines the rapprochement between the modern and classical schools of criminal law around 1900, the emergence of compromise proposals at the biennial congresses (Juristentage) of German-speaking jurists from 1900 to 1906, and the draft codes produced by Imperial Germany's official penal reform commissions from 1906 until 1914. The essay advances two central arguments. First, the classical school's endorsement of the dual-track system for recidivists and post-prison detention in an asylum for mentally abnormal offenders demonstrates that the classical school had, in fact, accepted the modern school's claim that mentally 'habitual criminals' as well as 'mentally abnormal' offenders posed serious threats to the social order that were not being sufficiently addressed by the existing legal system. Second, the conflict between the modern and classical schools was not about the question of whether measures based on an offender's 'dangerousness' (rather than the offense committed) were warranted; the majority of the classical school agreed that such measures, including indefinite detention, were warranted. Instead, the conflict concerned the different, narrower question of whether such measures should be imposed as part of the criminal justice system or whether they should be imposed outside this system, as extra-judicial measures, that is, in the form of administrative, police, welfare or medical measures. Therefore, the debate between the two schools was mostly a debate over what form social defense measures should take. Whereas the modern school called for a broader vision of criminal justice in the service of protecting society against dangerous individuals, the classical school sought to keep criminal justice narrowly focused on offense-based retributive justice and therefore insisted that social-defense measures based on dangerousness be farmed out to non-judicial state agencies.
540 _aAll rights reserved
_uhttp://oapen.org/content/about-rights
546 _aEnglish
650 7 _aCrime and criminology
_2bicssc
650 7 _aGeneral and world history
_2bicssc
650 7 _aLegal history
_2bicssc
653 _acriminal, criminological, law, reform, positivism
700 1 _aPifferi, Michele
_4oth
793 0 _aOAPEN Library.
856 4 0 _uhttps://library.oapen.org/handle/20.500.12657/52999
_70
_zFree-to-read: OAPEN Library: description of the publication
999 _c36761
_d36761